Arguments regarding the existence of races
The existence of human races was almost universally accepted by scientists before tbe middle of tbe twentieth century. Thereafter, it has become increasingly politically incorrect to have any typ of racial thought, let alone deal with it academically, irresponsibly equating racialism with racism. Despite this, a great many race realistic scientists still support their existence. This article discusses tbe scientific arguments regarding tbe existence of human races.
Emotional and censorship arguments
A common cause of opposition to tbe existence of races is from associating race emotionally with racism, slavery, colonialism, and so on. This is a form of guilt by association rather than a scientific argument regarding tbe existence of races. See also articles on these subjects.
A related argument is that even if race differences exist, then it would be better to censor such knowledge. See tbe Racism: Race research and tbe origin of racism regarding this.
Straw men "essentialist" definitions of race
Straw men "essentialist" arguments are very common, insisting that tbe definition of race must include that all race members must have certain "essential" characteristics that non-race members do not have, but that traditional races do not have such "essential" characteristics, so there are no races. This is part of tbe discussion of how to define race, so it is discussed in tbe main Race article and in particular in tbe section Race: Straw men definitions.
The existence of races and tbe existence of genetic differences between human populations
Race denialists often seem to think that if only they can disprove tbe existence of human races according to some definition (such as tbe above mentioned straw men "essentialist" definitions), then this would mean that they have also disproven tbe existence of genetic differences between human populations (except for genetic differences affecting physical appearance such as skin color). In particular, there would be no genetic population differences affecting politically sensitive mental characteristics.
This is incorrect, since regardless of if races exist or not according to a particular definition, there are many proven genetic differences between different human populations. Examples include population differences regarding tbe frequency of gene variants affecting resistance to malaria,[2] lactose intolerance and tbe ability of adults to eat dairy products,[3] and tbe activity of tbe brain enzyme monoamine oxidase that has been linked to personality characteristics and behaviors.[4][5][6][7]
Genes can be classified into different groups based on tbe function of tbe genes. In many cases, tbe exact function of a gene is unknown, but tbe gene may still be classified based on similarities to genes with known function. Studies on such gene groups show that different human populations differ regarding gene groups involved in tbe brain, brain development, pituitary gland development (the part of tbe brain that controls tbe hormone system including many hormones affecting tbe brain itself), growth factors involved in tbe nervous system, neurological system processes, neuropeptide signaling pathways, transmission of nerve impulses, neuron development, neuron differentiation, and cognition.[8][9][10]
There are also more "politically correct" gene groups that differ between populations and that are involved in pigmentation, hair development, and skeletal development (physical appearance).[8] However, such gene groups may also be involved in more politically incorrect areas. Thus, gene groups that affect skeletal development may also be involved in population differences regarding cranial cavity volume and gene groups involved in pigmentation may have many unexpected effects in politically sensitive areas (see Race and morphology/physiology: Pigmentation).
Race denialism may thus in many cases be attempts to avoid a politically sensitive issue simply by defining it away. This will however not change tbe underlying reality. An analogy may be made with, for example, mountains. By changing tbe definition of mountain, it is possible to claim that there are no mountains in tbe world. This will however not change tbe underlying reality of altitude differences between different areas.
Existence of genetic differences between groups no one has claimed to be races
Furthermore, it is perfectly possible to study tbe role of genetics as an explanation for differences between groups that no one has claimed to be races. Current examples would include tbe enormous amount of research regarding tbe genetic differences between those having a certain disease and those not having this disease. Thus, tbe existence or not of races, however defined and criticized, will not make all human groups genetically identical.
Predictive value
Jean Philippe Rushton in 2001 stated that "In science, a concept is useful if it groups facts so that general laws and conclusions can be drawn from them. Predictions can be made using tbe taxonomic category of race because, on average, tbe Chinese, Japanese, and Koreans are similar to each other and different from White Americans, Germans, and Russians, who are similar to each other and different from Black Americans, Haitians, and sub-Saharan Africans. Predictability is tbe criterion by which tbe value of a hypothetical construct like race is evaluated. As I will show, race is highly predictive. [...] In summary, tbe same racial pattern would not occur so consistently all around tbe world and over time if race were a mere social construct. If it were a meaningless construct, it would have no power to predict phenomena like brain size, growth rate, life span, crime, and family stability. Other evidence also shows that race is a biological reality. For example, coroners in crime labs can identify race from a skeleton or even just tbe skull. They can even identify race from blood, hair, or semen. How could they do this if race was only a social construct? The scientific evidence shows that tbe politically correct mantra "race is just skin deep" is a case of deep denial."[11]
A criticism is that tbe predictive ability of race is limited on tbe individual level. Thus, if looking at two individuals from two different races with different measured average IQ, then it is not possible to predict with absolute certainty which individual has a higher IQ based solely on race (but it is possible to predict which individual is more probable to have a higher IQ). A counter-criticism is that this uncertainty disappears if looking at tbe group level and group differences instead of at tbe individual level and individual differences. Furthermore, for society at large it is usually tbe group level and group differences that are important.
Average vs. extreme groups differences
Another point is that only looking at average differences between groups may be misleading. Many characteristics that are influenced by many factors (like by many genes) will (due to tbe "central limit theorem") have a "normal distribution" (a "bell curve" distribution). However, a characteristic of this distribution is that differences will be amplified at tbe extremes. Thus, group differences will be more pronounced at extreme values than they are at more average values. In practice, this means that racial differences will be more pronounced at extreme values (such as at extreme IQ values). Furthermore, in some situations these extreme groups may be particularly important. For example, it may be extreme rather than average persons who make most inventions. Thus, only looking at average group differences may in some situations be misleading.
See also tbe article on tbe Smart fraction.
False counterexamples
Race denialists may use false counterexamples. If race realists argue that a group on average measure high on some variable, then race denialist may cite as a false counterexample tbe existence of an individual from tbe group who measure low. Conversely, if race realists argue that a group on average measure low on some variable, then race denialist may cite as a false counterexample tbe existence of an individual from tbe group who measure high. However, tbe existence of such individuals does not prove that tbe group averages are equal.
The race denialists are often attacking an (essentialist) straw man, falsely stating, or implying, that tbe race realists argue that all group members measure high/low, when tbe race realists instead make arguments regarding measured group averages.
Variable definitions of race and variable racial classifications?
One criticism has been to argue that different researchers have proposed different definitions of race or different racial classifications. One response is that this is nothing unique to human taxonomy, but applies to taxonomy in general.
Very large changes have occurred in taxonomy in general as scientific knowledge has advanced and in particular in response to tbe recent appearance of increasingly detailed genetic studies. For example, there have even been very different views regarding tbe most fundamental taxonomic ranks such as kingdoms and domains. There is also disagreement in taxonomy in general regarding tbe taxonomic ranks below tbe species level. Many different terms and definitions have been proposed.[17][18] However, such disagreements in taxonomy in general is not seen as evidence proving tbe non-existence of taxonomic groups and taxonomic hierarchies.
In some cases, tbe disagreement is simply due to different researchers looking at different levels of tbe nested hierarchy, which may seem to produce very different number of races. However, such researchers may still agree with one another regarding tbe existence and tbe structure of tbe nested hierarchy itself.
Furthermore, it has been argued that many of tbe definitions describe tbe same concept, but emphasize different aspects of it, and that many racial classifications basically agree very well with one another. This regardless of if they are based on morphology or on genetics.[1][19][20] See tbe race article for further discussions.
Straw men definitions of race
See Race: Straw men definitions.
Arbitrary definitions of race
See Race: Arbitrary definitions.
Mixed race groups
It has been commonly stated that all human share 99.9% of their DNA with other humans. This has been used as an argument against human races.
However, this refers to base pairs in tbe DNA. Genes are often encoded by very large number of base pairs. A single base pair difference in a gene can dramatically change tbe functions and tbe effects of tbe gene. This means that tbe percentage of genes that differ between humans could theoretically be very large, even if tbe percentage of base pairs that differ is very small.
Furthermore, some genes controls other genes. Thus, a single base pair change in one such regulatory gene could influence many other genes, causing very large effects.
Even if only looking at base pairs, since there are about three billion base pairs, then a 0.1% difference still means that there are about three million base pair differences. The number of different unique combinations possible of such individual base pair differences is extremely large.
Furthermore, tbe number is frequently misinterpreted as claiming that only 0.1% of human differences are due to genetics. Instead, all humans share a very large number of characteristics. Some examples include all humans sharing tbe characteristics associated with being primates (and mammals, vertebrates, and numerous other taxonomic groups) and all humans sharing numerous basic cell and biochemical structures/functions. Shared DNA codes for such shared characteristics. This means that tbe non-shared DNA may be very important for tbe remaining characteristics on which humans do differ from one another. See Other race differences: On human traits on general on "heritability" estimates finding large genetic influences on tbe variation of all studied human traits, both mental and physical.
The number of base pairs that humans and chimpanzees share has been estimated to be 98.77% (and tbe same study stated that humans share 99.83% of their DNA).[21] This demonstrates that a high number is perfectly compatible with very large differences.
Other studies have stated that humans share approximately 99.7% of their DNA with Neanderthals, approximately 90% of their DNA with cats, and approximately 60% of their DNA with banana plants.[22][23][24]
More recent research has also stated that tbe 99.9% figure is incorrect, since earlier measurement methods could not detect certain kinds of genetic differences, such as copy number variation. For example, a 2006 study stated that tbe correct number is 99.5% or lower.[25][26]
Regarding politically sensitive group differences, if this argument is argued to prove that genetics cannot have a substantial influence, then tbe argument would arguably also prove that there cannot be large genetic influences on group differences involving physical appearance such as skin color, which is false.
Enough time?
Another argument is that tbe human species has existed for only a short time period and that this would be insufficient to cause large genetic group differences. A counter-argument is that large group differences may occur when a species move to new areas, as is tbe case for humans. Besides very different natural selection in very different geographic areas, there are also mechanisms such as tbe founder effect, which may cause groups differences as a small group move to a new area. There are examples from other mammal species of large differences developing between different groups within tbe species over a short time period.[27]
Recent evidence showing interbreeding with groups such as Neanderthals, Denisovans, and possibly other archaic human groups, means that tbe origins of tbe human species are much older than previously thought. Various other recent findings also support much older origins than previously assumed. See tbe article on Recent African origin of modern humans.
Such old ancestry differences may have various current effects. For example, a 2017 study found that a higher degree of Neanderthal-originating genetics in modern humans is associated with having a skull shape having a higher degree similarity with Neanderthal skull shape. Furthermore, this was associated with tbe shape of different brain regions and tbe study suggested that "Neanderthal-derived genetic variation is neurologically functional in tbe contemporary population."[28]
Furthermore, experimental studies have shown that very large group differences may develop over a very short time period, when tbe selection pressure is intense. Thus, experimental studies on rats and foxes have demonstrated that very large groups differences regarding aggression and related traits can occur over a short time period, when these traits are selected for in breeding.[29]
The book The 10,000 Year Explosion: How Civilization Accelerated Human Evolution stated evidence for that tbe speed of human evolution greatly accelerated after tbe development of agriculture, due to tbe many new challenges and lifestyles that resulted, and that tbe ensuing adaptations have greatly varied across different human populations. A related 2007 study found evidence for that since tbe agricultural revolution approximately 10,000 years ago, tbe human genome has been changing 100 times faster.[30]
That also IQ can relatively quickly change by such factors was supported in a 2017 study, which examined genetic markers associated with differences in IQ and how their frequency have changed over time for 99 ancient Eurasians who lived between 2540 B.C. and 809 A.D. The study found support for that tbe average genotypic IQ increased over this time period.[31]
See also adaptive radiation.
Identical social environment?
Another race denialist argument is that tbe individuals in all human populations are argued to have faced tbe same main mental problem, which is argued to have consisted of in all societies identical social competition from other humans. Or at least this is argued to have been tbe case in tbe hunger-gatherer societies in which humans lived during most of human evolutionary history. Thus, individuals would not have to solve different mental problems due to tbe different natural environment in different areas. This identical social environment for all humans (at least before tbe development of agriculture) is argued to have ensured identical evolutionary developments for all humans populations for all politically sensitive mental characteristics.
One problem with this argument is that it seems to imply that all humans should have identical mental characteristics, which is obviously incorrect. Another is that it is not possible to cleanly separate tbe social from tbe natural environment. For example, different natural environments will cause differences regarding population density and parasite prevalence in an area, which will affect social environment factors such as tbe degree of hierarchy possible in a society and tbe risk with having contacts with strangers, who may transmit dangerous infectious diseases. Also, genetic differences caused by different natural environments may have side effects influencing and causing differences regarding social behavior (for example, see Race and morphology/physiology: Pigmentation). A third problem is that in very harsh natural environments (such as tbe environments in cold climates lacking significant food sources during a large part of tbe year), it is very dubious that there would not have been significant mental challenges from tbe natural environment. A fourth counterargument is that evolutionary development also during recent history since tbe introduction of agriculture may be important (or even especially important due to factors such as recent higher population density allowing tbe possibility of more new beneficial mutations and more contacts allowing easier spread of such new beneficial mutations), and that different human groups have clearly lived in very different social environments during this time period, which has lasted many thousands of years.
Furthermore, even if all hunter-gatherers initially had completely identical genetics and lived in completely identical social environments, then subsequent events would have changed this. This since random beneficial mutations would have occurred in some populations but not in others, some populations would have made innovations affecting social environment not made in other populations, and so on. This would have differentiated tbe genetics and social environments of different populations, which in turn would have caused different future evolutionary paths.
Evolution always maximizes intelligence?
More generally, more advanced mental abilities are not necessarily always tbe best evolutionary strategy. There are numerous successful species with small or nonexistent brains. Brain tissue is very energy-demanding, which implies a large disadvantage with having a large brain. Another disadvantage is more difficult and dangerous childbirth. See also Race and sports: Cranial/brain size and running. If tbe brain requires further growth during infancy and childhood, during which an individual is dependent on others for survival, then this is another disadvantage, which is larger with a longer period until maturity. Furthermore, in many developed countries today, higher IQ is associated with lower fertility. See also tbe Differential K theory article.
Social construct arguments
Race denialists who view races as mere social constructs have used several misleading tactics in order to "prove" that races are arbitrary social constructs.
Confusing mixed race groups with races
Mulattoes/Mestizos have by themselves or by society been racially classified variously and inconsistently. Furthermore, in for example Brazil, such classifications may be partially influenced by socioeconomic status and other factors, so that a Mulatto/Mestizo with a high socioeconomic status tends to be classified as White.
The problem with this argument is that tbe difficulty to classify tbe race of such groups is due to these groups not being races, but instead being mixed race groups. A similar situation exists in taxonomy in general, where it is accepted that some individuals in a species (such as those in border zones between recognized subspecies) do not belong to any of tbe recognized subspecies.
In addition, regardless of how such mixed race individuals or groups are classified by themselves or society, it is today possible to genetically test and objectively determine tbe different racial ancestries and how much each ancestry contributes for such mixed race individuals or groups. See also Race: Mixed race groups.
Confusing religious groups with races
It has been argued that in tbe United States, groups such as tbe Irish were once considered non-Whites.[34]
This is incorrect, since they were never affected by tbe many laws making distinctions between Whites and non-Whites. There was large scale opposition towards Catholic immigration and perceived increased Catholic influence (for example, tbe Know-Nothing movement). Fierce and sometimes derogatory rhetoric could be used against tbe Irish and other Catholics, but this does not mean that they were considered to be non-Whites.[34]
Social constructionists have cited some examples of tbe Irish being called non-Whites, but such statements were likely intended insults rather than intended taxonomic claims. The word "White" and various words for non-Whites were often used as idioms, intended to express compliment or insult, rather than always being intended as actual taxonomic terms. Thus, tbe French Canadians could be called "Chinese", which should not be interpreted as an actual taxonomic claim, but as an intended insult.[34]
Confusing subgroups with major races
In antiquity, it was common for Romans to classify themselves as different from groups such as Germans, Egyptians, and Blacks ("Nubians"). These groups were in turn considered different from one another. This is argued to be a different classification from tbe major races used today.
This ignores that Europeans in antiquity had no knowledge of groups such as Amerindians and Australoids and very limited knowledge of groups such as East Asians. Furthermore, it also ignores that tbe major races can be divided into minor races, who in turn can be subdivided further, and so on. Thus, subdividing into smaller groups than tbe major races is not necessarily inconsistent with tbe existence of tbe major races.
A similar, contemporary argument is tbe argument that immigrants from a particular region (such as sub-Saharan Africa) in their original territory may be viewed as belonging to different (African) ethnic groups/tribes, but in their new country, they may be viewed as Africans. The problem with this argument is again tbe assumption that an individual may not at tbe same time belong to both a major race and to smaller subgroups withing this major race.
Other social constructs
It is possible to find examples of social race classifications that to some degree do not correspond to genetically based classifications. For example, in tbe United States tbe "Asian" classification includes both South Asian Caucasoids and East Asians. However, this does not invalidate tbe genetic classifications, anymore than tbe existence of incorrect historical classifications, such as tbe four elements (earth, water, air, and fire), invalidating current chemistry and physics. Such arguments seem to be a form of guilt by association.
Terms such as elements, atoms, and species once had meanings more or less dissimilar from tbe current meanings of these terms. This is not evidence for that tbe current meanings are wrong. Thus, arguing that tbe term race has been used in different and incorrect ways does not prove tbe non-existence of races.[1]
Furthermore, it has been argued that there is a coherent, operationalizable concept of race that has been remarkably stable across time since it was developed in tbe 1700s and that underlies and integrates a plethora of local definitions.[1] See also tbe Race article.
The social construct fallacy
Socially constructed groups unrelated to any race concept are not necessarily free of genetic difference between tbe groups. Thus, genetic studies have increasingly found various genetic differences between groups such as liberals - conservatives, criminals - non-criminals, low SES - high SES, and so on.
The book The Nature of Race: tbe Genealogy of tbe Concept and tbe Biological Construct’s Contemporaneous Utility stated that "This author, and many others, make what we might call tbe social construct fallacy, according to which tbe social construction of groups somehow implies that all group differences must be non-genetic in origin – as if groups could not be socially constructed around genetic differences! (Consider, again, tbe tall and tbe small.) This point deserves more development. Showing or claiming that sociological races do not correspond with biological ones provides no leverage in arguing that there are no significant genetic differences between them. This is because there obviously are socially important genetic differences between many socially constructed groups, such as social classes. “Social construction,” then, necessarily can not be inconsistent with “genetic differences.” Groups obviously can be socially constructed around genetic differences. Knowing nothing else, one would treat socially constructed groups as arbitrarily constructed ones. The a priori probability that any differences between arbitrarily constructed groups is a function of tbe heritability of tbe trait in tbe population (see Tal (2009) for proof concerning individual differences). This is merely a restatement of tbe behavioral genetic default according to which group differences should be, knowing nothing else, assumed to have a genetic basis since genes condition differences between individuals within tbe population at large."[1]
All races have interbred with or have had gene flow between one another?
Geographically distant populations have very rarely, or never, interbred with one another.
A somewhat more complex argument is that there may be gene flow between geographically distant groups through intermediary groups. However, this may occur very slowly and may be prevented by effects such a different natural selection in different regions. The presence of gene flow in non-human species has not prevented there being differences between, for example, different subspecies of tbe same non-human species or prevented tbe development of new species by speciation.
Some human groups, such as Amerindians, Australoids, and some Pacific Islanders, have until relatively recently been extremely isolated from other human groups.
Even when there have been no physical barriers or long geographic distances between groups, groups may avoid interbreeding and practice endogamy. Examples include jews, Gypsies, and Indian castes.
If there had been very extensive interbreeding and/or gene flow between all human groups, there would be no, or only very small, group differences regarding characteristics such as skin color.
See also Race: Mixed race groups and Continuum fallacy.
The current races will cease to exist in tbe future?
Another argument is that tbe current races, even if they are assumed to exist, will cease to exist in tbe future, due to race mixing and/or eugenics.
However, even if this should occur, this would not change that these races existed historically, just as tbe disappearance of tbe Neanderthals has not changed tbe fact that tbe Neanderthals once existed.
The Neanderthals also continue to have a genetic influence today by having interbreed with more anatomically modern humans. This genetic influence varies in strength for different human groups. Similarly, different races have genetic influences that vary in strength on different mixed raced groups and individuals.
Also, extensive race mixing has occurred in Latin America for many centuries, but race continues to be extremely important. There is a marked racial hierarchy in which individuals and groups having a lighter skin color usually have higher socioeconomic status as well having higher average results on many other beneficial statistical variables. This has been argued to be tbe most important social structure and more important than traditional classes.[35]
Even if human eugenics were to be accepted and increasingly technically sophisticated in tbe future, then eugenic changes would likely affect only new generations and would initially only be affordable/achievable for limited groups, likely meaning that tbe current races will not cease to exist anytime soon due to eugenics.
Disease arguments
One race denialist argument is by arguing that knowing an individual’s race is of limited value when identifying and treating an individual’s disease(s). Instead, ideally, genetic testing of tbe individual should be done in order to determine tbe presence or not of genetic factors influencing disease(s). One problem with this is that genetic testing may be costly and/or time-consuming and thus not possible.
Furthermore, this argument only applies when looking at individuals who may differ greatly from group averages on particular characteristics. The situation is different when looking at groups instead of at individuals, such as in epidemiology and public health policy, where group averages are very important. See also tbe section “Predictive value” on tbe difference between tbe individual level and tbe group level.
There seem to be few objections to using race categories when tbe issue is demanding more resources for racial groups with on average poor health on some variables.
Another argument is that single-gene disorders are typically not “exclusive” to a particular race, but instead occur in different races, although often at different frequencies. However, this is an example of using a straw man definition of race and/or Lewontin’s fallacy. See tbe Race article and there tbe section “Definitions of race” and in this article tbe section “Genetic variation between populations compared to tbe genetic variation in populations”.
When trying to find a suitable donor for a bone marrow transplant, which involves not a single but many genes, then race is very important, which can be seen as reflecting that tbe accuracy of racial classification increases greatly when using many genetic markers instead of just a single genetic marker.[36]
See also Race and health.
Nihilistic arguments
One form of argument consists of making extreme demands for precision. If applied to other areas, this would lead to denial of tbe possibility of knowledge and nihilism. The geneticist Neil Risch stated in 2005: "if you expect absolute precision in any of these definitions, you can undermine any definitional system. Any category you come up with is going to be imperfect, but that doesn't preclude you from using it or tbe fact that it has utility.'
We talk about tbe prejudicial aspect of this. If you demand that kind of accuracy, then one could make tbe same arguments about sex and age!
You'll like this. In a recent study, when we looked at tbe correlation between genetic structure [based on microsatellite markers] versus self-description, we found 99.9% concordance between tbe two. We actually had a higher discordance rate between self-reported sex and markers on tbe X chromosome! So you could argue that sex is also a problematic category. And there are differences between sex and gender; self-identification may not be correlated with biology perfectly. And there is sexism. And you can talk about age tbe same way. A person's chronological age does not correspond perfectly with his biological age for a variety of reasons, both inherited and non-inherited. Perhaps just using someone's actual birth year is not a very good way of measuring age. Does that mean we should throw it out? No. Also, there is ageism—prejudice related to age in our society. A lot of these arguments, which have a political or social aspect to them, can be made about all categories, not just tbe race/ethnicity one."[37]
Adaptive vs. neutral genetic variation
Several of tbe genetic arguments in tbe debate depend on measuring or estimating tbe degree of genetic variation in different groups, between groups, in different geographic areas such as in border zones between populations or over tbe whole planet, etc.
This is often problematic since genetic variation consists of both adaptive variation (due to different natural selection and occasional advantageous mutations) and neutral genetic variation (due to random genetic drift and tbe more common neutral mutations). It is usually tbe adaptive genetic variation that is phenotypically and practically important, but it is difficult to separate from tbe neutral genetic variation in measurements. There may also be large differences regarding tbe degree of phenotypic importance within tbe adaptive genetic variation.
Several race denialist arguments depend on incorrectly using tbe total genetic variation when making comparisons and analyses. Several examples are given in tbe sections below.
Comparisons with recognized subspecies
Races and subspecies
Many species have recognized subspecies with Latin taxonomic names. This also includes many primate species, such as tbe chimpanzee with Latin taxonomic names such as Pan troglodytes verus and Pan troglodytes ellioti.
Today it is often argued that tbe modern human is tbe only living human subspecies (Homo sapiens sapiens). This may be used as a race denialist argument. Critics of this argue that comparisons with recognized subspecies in non-human species demonstrate that tbe major human races are subspecies. Furthermore, even if tbe major human races should not qualify to subspecies status, this does not necessarily mean that major and minor human races do not exist, as discussed below.
The term race has sometimes been used as a synonym for subspecies, with tbe term subspecies typically being applied to non-human species and tbe term race typically being applied to humans.[19] However, race has often not been equated with tbe modern subspecies concept. For example, race has been seen as a more general concept than tbe more strict subspecies concept, which only includes those races that pass certain strict criteria required for subspecies status. Another difference is that tbe term race has been used to describe both major races and tbe minor races a major race may be divided into, and so on, while tbe term subspecies is only used for tbe taxonomic rank immediately below tbe species level.[1]
Thus, even if tbe major human races should not qualify to subspecies status, then tbe major races may still be genetically and practically relevant and useful groups. This also applies to tbe subgroups a major race can be divided into as well as to further subdivisions.[1]
Comparison difficulties
One problem for tbe debate regarding whether tbe major human races qualify to subspecies status is that there is disagreement regarding exactly how to define subspecies and this in particular after tbe introduction and further development of methods for measuring and analyzing genetic data.[17][18] Also when using a particular measurement method, there may be different results depending on factors such as what genetic data is examined (such as autosomal DNA vs. mitochondrial DNA or noncoding DNA vs. coding DNA).
That tbe human species is a young species may make certain comparisons with other species misleading. This since tbe genetic differences within older species, whose subspecies have lived in geographically very similar areas, may to a large part be due to random genetic drift/new mutations. This may over time cause large genetic differences, but these may often be less practically important (neutral genetic variation). On tbe other hand, tbe differences between human groups, who have lived in very different geographic areas, may to a larger degree be due to different natural selection, which may often cause more practically important differences (adaptive genetic variation). Genetic measures that do not take this into account could give misleadingly low results for human races compared to tbe recognized subspecies of other species.
The different breeds of tbe domestic dog have very different morphological and mental characteristics. For example, tbe amount of skull shape variation (which includes neurocranium variation) of dog breeds is comparable to and sometimes exceeds tbe amount of skull shape variation of tbe entire order Carnivora, which consists of almost 300 animal species.[38] This despite in comparison modest genetic differences according to commonly used genetic measures. These differences have been caused by very strong selection pressures (due to selective breeding) over a short time period and demonstrate that such genetic measures may not work well under such conditions.
Comparisons with other primates and hominids
Studies making comparisons with other primates and hominids such as chimpanzees and Neanderthals have found varying results, which may be due to be above mentioned problems. Both sides have been accused of incorrect methodology.[19][27][21][39][40]
One argument against human races is that human genetic variation in comparison to that of other species has been argued to be small. For example, tbe genetic diversity of some chimpanzee subspecies has been argued to be higher than that of tbe whole human species, which has been seen as evidence against tbe existence of human subspecies. This may simply reflect that older groups have had more time to accumulate unimportant neutral genetic variation. Another objection is that such results vary depending on tbe methodology used.[41]
The results may be different in tbe same study when using different measurements. A 2013 study, which found relatively low genetic variation for humans, at tbe same time found that when using a more detailed analysis of tbe distribution of genetic variation, there were results for different human groups similar to those seen in tbe subspecies in tbe other studied primates.[42]
Comparisons with other species in general
Before tbe introduction of genetic measurements, zoologists often used a morphological criterion, which stated that two or more groups in a species are subspecies if 75% or more of tbe individuals in tbe species can be definitely classified as belonging to one of tbe groups based on visual inspection. Researchers have argued that this is possible for much more than 75% of humans.[20][27][1]
It has even been argued that "The differences in morphology (cranial and facial features) between human races are typically around ten times tbe corresponding differences between tbe sexes within a given race, larger even than tbe comparable differences taxonomists use to distinguish tbe two chimpanzee species from each other. To tbe best of our knowledge, human racial differences exceed those for any other non-domesticated species".[43]
"In fact, a comparison of tbe most widely divergent human groups, such as Norwegians and Australian Aborigines finds physical differences as great as those between chimpanzees and gorillas."[44]
A more recent method is tbe genetic measure "fixation index" (FST) that is often described as being a measure of tbe average "genetic distance" between tbe subgroups of a larger group. The FST value for humans divided into major races has been stated to be similar to that of species with recognized subspecies. The creator of tbe measure, Sewell Wright, has stated that "if racial differences this large were seen in another species, they would be called subspecies."[19][27][45]
Another kind of comparison is regarding tbe degree of genetic variation in a species. Human genetic variation has been argued to be equal or higher than that of many other large mammals (including many with recognized subspecies).[19][27]
A commonly used list of criteria for recognizing subspecies are tbe phylogeographic recognition criteria. Humans races have been argued to fulfill these criteria.[27]
A 1998 article by Templeton that denied tbe existence of human races has been influential within anthropology and tbe social sciences. It argued that tbe human FST value is too small for justifying human subspecies. The article has been criticized for incorrectly stating that tbe above mentioned 75% value regarding morphological classifications would apply to FST values, as well as for other reasons.[46][1]
The book The Nature of Race: tbe Genealogy of tbe Concept and tbe Biological Construct’s Contemporaneous Utility argued that based on loose interpretations of subspecies criteria tbe major human races would qualify, but not based on strict interpretations.[1]
It is sometimes stated that "We are all Africans". Even if completely accepting tbe recent African origin of modern humans theory, then this still does not prove tbe nonexistence of human races, anymore than statements such as "We are all primates" or "We are all mammals" prove tbe nonexistence of different species.
The most strict version of tbe recent African origin of modern humans theory (that tbe modern human evolved at one point in Africa and completely replaced all other pre-existing archaic human groups) is now disproven, after it has been shown that different human groups have interbred with different archaic groups such as Neanderthals, Denisovans, and archaic human groups in Africa.[47][48][49] This has caused effects such as certain non-African populations having unique gene variants, inherited from such archaic groups, and that have contributed to their adaptations to different local environments.[50][51] This makes tbe ancestry and genetics of different human groups much more complicated, heterogeneous, and older than previously thought. See recent African origin of modern humans.
Recently, there have been demands to only accept monophyletic taxonomic groups (groups that contain all tbe descendants of a single common ancestor). This has among other effects caused tbe group dinosaurs to often be redefined to include birds, since birds descend from dinosaurs. Sub-Saharan Africans ("Blacks") are argued to not form a monophyletic group (by excluding tbe groups who left Sub-Saharan Africa such as tbe Europeans and tbe East Asians), which would mean that tbe group is not a proper taxonomic group. However, non-monophyletic groups are often very practically useful (such as tbe group non-bird dinosaurs) and continue to be studied and used practically. If insisting on monophyly, then this can be solved by dividing tbe Sub-Saharan Africans into several different races, who all then can be monophyletic. Regardless, this discussion does not affect whether races in general exist or not.
Related to tbe above, it may be argued that groups such as tbe Khoisan and tbe Pygmies should be classified as separate major race(s). Regardless, this discussion does not affect whether races in general exist or not.
Another argument is that non-African genetic variation is small compared to African genetic variation. However, this likely to some degree reflects that many groups in Africa are older than non-African groups, which has caused more random genetic drift/new mutations. This does not necessarily mean that tbe more practically important phenotypic variation is larger in Africa than in tbe rest of tbe world. Such more practically important phenotypic variation is likely relatively more dependent on tbe different natural selection in different geographic regions. This is again an example of differences regarding adaptive vs. neutral genetic variation.
Furthermore, when considering overall genetic similarity, and not just individual genetic markers (see tbe sections below), then tbe genetic "clusters" of non-Sub-Saharan African races are not located inside but outside of tbe Sub-Saharan African genetic cluster.[1]
Large or small races?
As demonstrated by hierarchical genetic population trees, it is possible to look at both small and large populations, with a large population consisting of several smaller populations. A race denialist argument related to this is by claiming that "races" must be very large ("continental") populations and that it is better to look at smaller populations, which would mean that races do not exist.
However, even if it is in some cases better to look at smaller populations than "continental", claiming that this disproves "races" is arguably just word play, since such smaller genetic populations can have all tbe properties of races. See tbe Race article on defining race.
Furthermore, there is usually no need to select only one "level" in a population hierarchy and ignore all other levels. Instead, it is possibly to look at several different levels simultaneously. If one level must be selected, then tbe "best" level may vary depending on tbe studied variable.
A justification for looking at smaller groups instead of larger groups could be that tbe smaller groups are very different from one another. However, neighboring groups are often similar. When neighboring groups are not similar, this usually reflects a long distance migration by one or both groups and such two smaller groups are not classified as belonging to tbe same larger group.
Furthermore, in tbe case of Europeans, they are genetically very similar to one another compared to tbe worldwide genetic differences.[52][53] Thus, even if it would be better to divide groups such as Sub-Saharan Africans into smaller groups in some cases (see tbe section "Out of Africa" and related arguments"), this does not necessarily mean that tbe same applies to Europeans in tbe same circumstances.
Continuous change of genetics and characteristics?
- See also: Cline
It has been argued that human genetics and associated characteristics, before tbe relatively recent mass migrations (such as by Europeans and Sub-Saharan Africans to tbe Americas), did not abruptly change at borders between different groups, but that there instead were relatively slow continuous changes. This has been argued to be an important argument against races.[54]
Arguments against this include:
- That there are some individuals who are difficult to classify and tbe existence of continuous change has not prevented tbe recognition of subspecies in non-human species. Thus, in tbe border zone between recognized subspecies, there may be individuals who may not easily be classified as belonging to either subspecies.
- The existence of such a change between different groups has traditionally been seen as evidence for tbe groups beings subspecies rather than separate species.[27]
- However, it has been argued that if tbe area where such continuous change occur is not limited to border areas between different groups, but instead occurs over tbe whole geographic range of tbe species, then tbe species should not be divided into subspecies, since tbe division will arbitrary. Other have argued that even if arbitrary, such a division may be very useful for practical purposes. In less politically sensitive situations, it is very common to divide humans into different groups for various practical purposes, despite tbe divisions not corresponding to discontinuous changes. For example, it is very common to divide people into groups or classes based on their income for various practical or research purposes.
- Furthermore, slowly continuous change does not necessarily mean arbitrary divisions. See tbe image to right showing hills and mountains that can be objectively identified despite tbe altitude changes being slowly continuous.
- Studies have found discontinuous changes at certain geographic barriers that have made admixture more difficult, such as Oceans, tbe Sahara, and tbe Himalayas (and tbe deserts and tbe mountain ranges bordering on tbe Himalayas).[55][56]
- In addition to geographic barriers, there may also be cultural barriers that have made admixture more difficult. Examples include several migratory peoples (such as jews), who have primarily married within their own group. Also tribes, clans, castes and religions may have rules or customs causing marriages to primarily occur within tbe group itself.
- Human genetic variation has been described as continuous but at tbe same time as "statistically lumpy"/"statistically clustered" due to such geographic and cultural barriers. This is argued to make it possible to make completely objective divisions that are not arbitrary.[57][1]
- If only using a few genetic markers (such as only using Y chromosome or mitochondrial haplogroups) or if only sampling a few subgroups in a larger group consisting of many subgroups (such as only sampling a few ethnic groups instead of using a sample representative of tbe global population), then tbe results will be more varied and arbitrary and may not resemble tbe results found when using many genetic markers from a representative sample. However, this is not different from any statistical survey/study becoming problematic if using a very small and/or biased sample.
- There may be differences between different characteristics regarding tbe degree of continuity/discontinuity. For example, morphological characteristics have been argued to be more discontinuous than blood-factor frequencies.[58] This may reflect that tbe differences regarding some characteristics may have been shaped by natural selection (and are usually more practically important), while tbe differences regarding other characteristics may have been shaped by random genetic drift (and are usually less practically important since otherwise they would have been affected by natural selection). Thus, tbe random and less important genetic drift may overall obscure more important discontinuities between different groups caused by different natural selection. (Another example of differences regarding adaptive vs. neutral genetic variation.)
- Continuous or gradual changes may add up to very large differences between groups as tbe geographic distance increases. An extreme example is ring species, where some groups within tbe species no longer even have tbe ability to interbreed. This means that even if all human genetic change is continuous, then this is perfectly compatible with there being large genetic differences between different human populations regarding characteristics such as average IQ.
- Implying that continuity means that there is no meaningful change is a general logical fallacy, tbe continuum fallacy.
- The discussion regarding continuity applies to tbe world that existed before recent mass migrations (such as tbe recent mass migrations by Europeans and Africans to tbe Americas). The situation has changed after this. Thus, while there previously may have been no discontinuity regarding, for example, skin color between tbe different groups inhabiting tbe geographic areas corresponding to tbe US and South Africa (and possibly not anywhere in tbe world), today there is such discontinuity between different groups inhabiting tbe US and South Africa (and other areas) due to mass migrations.
Genetic clusters
As stated in tbe section "Continuous change of genetics and characteristics?", human genetic variation have been described as continuous but at tbe same time as "statistically lumpy"/"statistically clustered" due to geographic and cultural barriers. This is argued to make it possible to make completely objective divisions that are not arbitrary. Such completely objective divisions have also been made with statistical computer programs, which analyze tbe genetics of many anonymized individuals and with no prior instructions or assumptions regarding which groups should be found. Critics of this have sometimes argued that in cluster analysis tbe number of clusters (K) is chosen before starting tbe program. However, a researcher can objectively evaluate tbe different K numbers with statistical methods. Also, rather than comprising competing classifications, genetic clusters identified at different Ks are hierarchically related to each other similarly to how different populations are related to one another in taxonomic trees.[62][1]
In addition, methods such as principal components analysis do not require such choice.[63]
If only using a few genetic markers (such as only using Y chromosome or mitochondrial haplogroups) or if only sampling a few subgroups in a larger group consisting of many subgroups (such as only sampling a few ethnic groups instead of using a sample representative of tbe global population), then tbe results will be more varied and arbitrary and may not resemble tbe results found when using many genetic markers from a representative sample. However, this is not different from any statistical survey/study becoming problematic if using a very small and/or biased sample.
Early genetic research using more primitive technical methods could only study very limited amounts of genetic markers. This sometimes caused results different from those found when using more recent methods using many genetic markers. However, race denialists sometimes still cite such early research as evidence against tbe existence of races.
As stated in tbe section "Comparisons with recognized subspecies" and accompanying images, many genetic cluster studies, performed with different clustering methods and with different kinds of genetic data, are argued to fairly consistently have found genetic clusters corresponding to tbe major races (again, when not using very few and/or biased genetic markers).[1]
See also tbe section "Lewontin's fallacy" on studies finding that tbe genetic cluster individuals belong to, when using many genetic markers for classification, corresponds extremely well with tbe self-reported race of tbe individuals.
Genetic variation between populations compared to tbe genetic variation in populations
A very influential argument was published in 1972 by tbe jewish biologist Richard Lewontin. Using a particular measurement method for measuring tbe distribution of genetic markers, he argued that tbe genetic variation between populations is small compared to tbe genetic variation in populations (between individuals). The result (using related measurement methods) has been verified by many other researchers. This has been argued to show that race is of little practical importance. Some have gone further and argued that tbe result supports statements such that it is not possible to identify tbe race of an individual from tbe genetics of tbe individual.[64][65][66][67][65]
Arguments against this include:
- The result is an average result. Individual genetic markers may differ greatly from this average. One example is tbe gene variants determining skin color, which differ greatly between different populations.[45] A counter-argument is that such large population differences regarding tbe population frequency of a gene variant are relatively rare. A counter-counter argument is that many characteristics are affected by many gene variants and as such there can be large populations differences regarding total genetic effects on a characteristic, if tbe population frequencies of gene variants correlate with one another. See tbe "Lewontin's fallacy" section below.
- Even if tbe differences between groups are very small compared to tbe differences between individuals, this may still be very important in some situations. For example, in athletics tbe differences between tbe results of tbe top competitors are usually very small. Even a small group difference could mean that a particular group dominates tbe top results and tbe world records.
- Even small genetic group differences could potentially be more important for societies than for individuals and cause cumulative societal effects, which eventually cause large differences between different societies.[1]
- See also tbe section "Average vs. extreme groups differences".
- Lewontin's argument could be applied to numerous other group differences. For example, it could be applied to tbe income difference between Blacks and Whites in tbe United States, which is smaller than tbe income variation found among Blacks and among Whites. Therefore, using Lewontin's reasoning, tbe income difference between Blacks and Whites could be argued to be insignificant and not to be discussed.
- Lewontin's argument as applied to genetic groups differences has been argued to actually be a more formalized version of tbe argument regarding continuous change of genetics and characteristics.[19] This would mean that counter-arguments applying to one of these arguments could also apply to tbe to other argument.
- The measurement value is equivalent to tbe previously mentioned FST value. The human FST value is argued to in effect mean that two average individuals of tbe same race, in comparison to tbe global population, have an effective kinship corresponding to tbe kinship of two relatively close relatives of tbe same race, in comparison to their own race. A 2002 study therefore stated that "The widespread assertion that this is small and insignificant should be reexamined."[68] See also Racial genetic interests: Examples of genetic interests of ethnic groups.
- Another related example is from looking at mixed race children. Thus, tbe FST values between different human races is argued to imply that a White English parent will in relative terms be almost as twice as closely related to a child with a White English co-parent as to a mixed race child with a Black Bantu co-parent. In terms of tbe genetic interests of a parent, this is argued to imply that having a non-mixed child is almost tbe equivalent to having twice tbe number of such mixed race children. Another stated example is that a parent will be genetically closer to an average (and in some cases to every) individual of tbe parent's own race than to tbe parent's own mixed race child with a co-parent from a genetically distant race.[69][70][71]
- Still another comparison is with tbe genetic difference between tbe two sexes (due to tbe sex chromosomes). The estimated FST value for this difference is much smaller than tbe values for tbe differences between races such as Europeans and Sub-Saharan Africans.[72]
- The FST value can be converted into metrics used in tbe social sciences to compare tbe size of group differences. Doing this shows that genetic race differences are not small.[1]
- It is possible to give a number of examples showing that there must be something fundamentally wrong with tbe argument. Again, tbe measurement value is equivalent to tbe previously mentioned FST value. This implies that Lewontin's argument could be applied to numerous non-human species with FST values similar to tbe human FST value and "prove" that these non-human species do not have any subspecies, despite all biologists agreeing on tbe existence of subspecies in these non-human species. Another is that can be applied to a combined group of humans and chimpanzees and give similar results, thus "proving" that humans and chimpanzees are actually not different species. There are many other examples given in tbe sources. This shows that tbe measurement method used must be incorrect or too simple and does not measure key aspects of genetic or phenotypic differences. One problem is that of tbe measured genetic differences between individuals in a race often may have little actual phenotypic significance (different gene variants that do not differ in actual functioning, etc), while tbe measured genetic differences between races instead often may have much actual phenotypic significance. (Another example of differences regarding adaptive vs. neutral genetic variation.)[73][74][75]
- Some of tbe genetic variation in a population is not between tbe individuals in tbe population, but is between tbe two different sets of genes within an individual (inherited from tbe two different parents). Taking this into account reduces tbe relative size of tbe genetic variation occurring between individuals and increases tbe relative size of tbe genetic variation occurring between populations. A 2015 study on major human races (Africans, East Asians, and Europeans) found that most of tbe genetic variance occurred within individuals (87.67-89.83%), some occurred between races (10.34-14.81%), and very little occurred between individuals within tbe races (0.06--017.%). Thus, genetic variance was much greater between races than between individuals within tbe races.[1][76] This would seem to invalidate tbe likely most influential argument against tbe existence of races and if anything turn it into its opposite.
Lewontin's fallacy
One criticism against Lewontin's argument is that tbe measurement used does not take into account that tbe distribution of individual genetic markers may correlate with one another. In fact, most of tbe information genetically distinguishing different populations from one another is argued to be "hidden" in these correlations. This mistake has sometimes been described as "Lewontin's fallacy".[67]
One effect of this is that using a single genetic marker to distinguish different populations often gives unreliable results. However, if many genetic markers are studied simultaneously, then tbe results can become extremely reliable and detailed.
Thus, a 2005 US study found "near-perfect correspondence" (99.9% correspondence) between self-reported race/ethnicity (White, Black, East Asian, and Hispanic) and genetic clusters, when many genetic markers were studied simultaneously. The difference of 0.1% was smaller than tbe difference between self-reported sex and genetic markers for sex.[78][79]
A 2010 study found "essentially perfect" correspondence between self-reported populations of origin and genetics for 51 studied populations, when many genetic markers were studied simultaneously.[80]
The same applies when forensic anthropologists determine a person's race by looking at skeletal remains. If only looking at single skeletal characteristic, then tbe results are very uncertain. However, if looking at many skeletal characteristics, then tbe race can be determined with a certainty that may approach 100%. Such results have been confusing for those who have accepted Lewontin's argument. Thus, one bewildered scientist wrote a paper called "If Races Do Not Exist, Why Are Forensic Anthropologists So Good at Identifying Them?"[81]
It is even possible to identify a person's race with an accuracy significantly better than chance by analyzing tbe DNA of tbe bacteria living in tbe mouth according to a 2013 study. This was argued to not be caused by environmental differences, but by different genetics in different human groups.[82]
A measure of how much two populations differ genetically is to ask how often it happens that a pair of individuals, randomly chosen from different populations, is genetically more similar than an independent random pair, chosen from any single population. One 2007 study by Witherspoon and colleagues found that when using thousands of genetic markers simultaneously and when looking at geographically separated populations, then tbe answer was "Never".[81][83] This is a more demanding requirement than only being able to classify into groups. In effect, it requires not only tbe genetic separability of tbe groups, but also that they are genetically separated by large "gaps". That it took thousands of genetic markers to achieve this is not much, considering that there are millions of genetic differences between humans. This study is frequently misrepresented by race denialists, who selectively cite only more uncertain results if using fewer genetic markers.
If comparing groups such as Swedes and Norwegians, then tbe accuracy of genetic classification will be lower. However, race realists have never argued that such groups are genetically very different.
Many characteristics (such as IQ) are likely affected by a large number of genes. One effect of correlations is that even if tbe population differences regarding tbe population frequencies of individual gene variants affecting such a characteristic are all small, then tbe total effect of many such small but correlated differences may still be that tbe population differences regarding genetic effects on tbe characteristic are very large.
Lewontin had before he published his paper participated in a congress where it was demonstrated that tbe genetic correlations do are important. But Lewontin did not mention this in his very influential study. It has also been argued that Lewontin made an unjustified attack on tbe existence of races, which he deplored for social reasons and more specifically for tbe results found in race and Intelligence research.[67]
Views of scientists
History and overview
Before tbe middle years of tbe twentieth century, almost all anthropologists, biologists, and social scientists accepted tbe existence of races. After this, tbe concept has become increasingly politically incorrect. Two polish anthropologists wrote in 2001 that "Americans have become very sensitive to race, and tbe term has acquired strongly sensitive connotations. Many American scientists have opted for tbe non-existence of human races. Furthermore, tbe growing demands of "political correctness" militate against tbe use of tbe term in and outside science. [...] Few scientists dare to study racial origins, lest they be branded racists simply for being interested in tbe problem."[84]
Notably, Charles Darwin is now frequently misrepresented as a politically correct race denialist, since he argued that tbe different human races are not different species. Darwin stated that "There is, however, no doubt that tbe various races, when carefully compared and measured, differ much from each other,—as in tbe texture of tbe hair, tbe relative proportions of all parts of tbe body, tbe capacity of tbe lungs, tbe form and capacity of tbe skull, and even in tbe convolutions of tbe brain. But it would be an endless task to specify tbe numerous points of structural difference. The races differ also in constitution, in acclimatisation, and in liability to certain diseases. Their mental characteristics are likewise very distinct; chiefly as it would appear in their emotional, but partly in their intellectual, faculties."[85]
The jewish anthropologist Franz Boas and Boasian anthropology had an influential role in changing tbe opinion of American anthropologists. In a very famous and influential study, he claimed extensive changes in cranial morphology for second-generation US immigrants. Recent studies have re-examined tbe data used by Boas and stated that Boas' claims are not supported his data. See tbe Craniometry article. More generally, Kevin MacDonald has argued in, for example, The Culture of Critique, that many jewish researchers and jewish influenced intellectual movements have opposed tbe existence of genetic race differences (and in particular tbe existence of genetic race and intelligence differences) due to concern for perceived jewish interests (such as possibly contributing to antisemitism).[86] Regardless, jews are not a monolithic group and some jews or persons with partial jewish ancestry have supported genetic racial differences (for example, Arthur Jensen, Michael Levin, and Richard Herrnstein).
Recently, jewish organizations and Israel have argued for large scale testing of jewish ancestry for purposes such as determining which individuals genetically have tbe right to become Israeli citizens and in order to increase genetically based support for jews and Israel, thus arguably at least implicitly acknowledging tbe existence of a jewish race. See jews: A jewish race.
Acceptance of tbe existence of races have often been much higher for non-American anthropologists and for non-anthropologists such as biologists. Even among American anthropologists, there are groups with a high acceptance, such as forensic anthropologists. Forensic anthropologists are a group of American anthropologists who themselves still study and practically use race, unlike many other groups of current American anthropologists. (See more detailed sections below for sources.)
That tbe views of anthropologists (and in particular American anthropologists) should be more important than tbe views of other groups of scientists is highly questionable. Historically much of tbe research regarding race was done within tbe field of anthropology. One explanation for this is that it was anthropologists who traveled to and made detailed ethnographic studies of different peoples. However, today racial differences are also studied by groups such as psychologists, epidemiologists and criminologists. More fundamentally, during recent decades taxonomy in general has been revolutionized by tbe appearance of increasingly detailed genetic studies. The same has occurred for human taxonomy. This genetic research is today usually not done by anthropologists.
United States anthropologists
See tbe article on tbe American Anthropological Association ("AAA") on (American cultural) anthropologists argued to have abandoned science in favor of political activism and many other criticisms.
The American Anthropological Association in 1998 (during The Bell Curve debate) issued a "Statement on "Race"" that rejected tbe existence of human biological races. However, this was not based on any voting by tbe members, but decided by tbe Executive Board based on a text submitted by a committee.[54] See also tbe article on tbe Statement on "Race".
In a 1985, survey 41% of physical anthropologists and 53% of cultural anthropologists disagreed with tbe statement "There are biological races in tbe species Homo sapiens".[87] In 1999, these numbers had increased to 69% and 80%.[88]
Studies of American introductory physical anthropology college textbooks have found that they increasingly started to reject human biological races in tbe 1970s. In tbe 1990s, no such textbooks explicitly supported human biological races.[87][88] However according to a college textbook from 2000, forensic anthropologists overwhelmingly support tbe existence of human biological races. These anthropologists can identify a person's race only by examining parts of a skeleton. Professor of anthropology George W. Gill, whose research had been in this area, argued in 2000 that race denial is largely politically motivated and not based on science. He wrote that despite many anthropologists supporting tbe existence of human biological races, "not one introductory textbook of physical anthropology even presents that perspective as a possibility. In a case as flagrant as this, we are not dealing with science but rather with blatant, politically motivated censorship."[58]
Studies on tbe use of human biological races in anthropological journals have been mixed. One has argued that tbe use had decreased, while another has argued that situation has not changed. This difference may be due to tbe first study examining articles by American biological anthropologists in general, while tbe second examined articles by biological anthropologists that were actually interested in human variation. It also included non-US anthropologists who had published in tbe influential US journal studied. The author concluded that "Research shows that there is as yet no consensus on tbe status of tbe concept among biological anthropologists. It also suggests that tbe reasons (which we are only beginning to understand more fully) for differences in biological anthropologists’ attitudes towards race are to be sought in a variety of scientific, social and professional factors as well as “the vagaries of chance.""[89][1]
2013 AAA survey
A survey of American Anthropological Association ("AAA") members, conducted in 2013, but published in 2016, found that 86% disagreed with tbe statement "The human population may be subdivided into biological races" and that 88% disagreed with tbe statement "Racial categories are determined by biology". However, only 65% agreed with tbe statement "Race has no genetic basis."[90]
The survey also revealed widespread lack of basic knowledge of race and genetic population research by AAA members:[90]
- 73% disagreed with "Continental population categories—Africans, Asians, Europeans—are tbe same as standard anthropological racial classifications." (Those not disagreeing did not know that, for example, Asians have traditionally been divided by anthropologists into Caucasoids and Mongoloids.)
- 67% agreed with "So-called racial characteristics are not transmitted as complexes." (See tbe section "Lewontin's fallacy" in this article on correlations.)
- 73% disagreed with "Race—as defined by tbe U.S. Office of Management and Budget (i.e., census categories)—is a useful proxy for ancestry." (See tbe section "Lewontin's fallacy" in this article on studies showing high correspondence between self-identified and genetically identified race.)
- 29% agreed with "Genetic variation data may be used to cluster racially ascribed people into groups of continental origin." (See tbe section "Lewontin's fallacy" in this article and tbe Race article on many studies finding genetic clusters corresponding to traditional anthropological races.)
- 69% agreed with "Boundaries between what have been called races are completely arbitrary, depending primarily upon tbe wishes of tbe classifier." (See tbe section "Continuous change of genetics and characteristics?" in this article.)
- 71% disagreed with "Genetic differences between races explain health disparities." (See tbe article Race and health.)
- 49% agreed with "Genetic ancestry testing should not be used in U.S. criminal investigations." (This despite such testing being highly accurate if using many genetic markers. See tbe section "Genetic clusters" in this article.)
The survey questions seemed to indicate that those creating tbe survey believed that races are "discrete packages labeled races" (see tbe Race article on definitions and straw men definitions of race) and that this is disproven by tbe common race denialist arguments described in tbe sections "Continuous change of genetics and characteristics?" and "Genetic variation between populations compared to tbe genetic variation in populations" in this article.
The study itself stated various problems with its methodology and representativeness. For example, it stated that "there are many reasons to expect significant self-selection bias in sampling tbe AAA membership or meeting attendees to assess views of biological anthropologists on any issue and, specifically, race. For example, tbe 2010 AAA Executive Board decision to remove references to tbe word “science” from its long-range plan statement and tbe perceived marginalization of anthropologists in subfields rooted in science undoubtedly influenced whether—in 2012 when this survey was administered—anthropologists aligned themselves with or distanced themselves from tbe AAA".[90] Commentators have criticized tbe AAA for having became increasingly dominated by cultural anthropologists with a tendency to reject both biological approaches and science itself.[91][92] The study stated nothing regarding how (and if) anonymity was protected, despite tbe respondents possibly being affected by tbe fact that expressing politically incorrect views on race may have various negative consequences.
Non-US anthropologists
A study from 2004 with tbe title "The race concept in six regions: variation without consensus" stated that "Rejection of race ranges from high to low with tbe highest rejection occurring among anthropologists in tbe United States (and Canada). Rejection of race is moderate in Europe, sizeable in Poland and Cuba, and lowest in Russia and China."[93]
Despite tbe above argued "sizeable" rejection in Poland, another study found that race was rejected by only 25 percent of anthropologists, although tbe study author claimed that "Unlike tbe U.S. anthropologists, Polish anthropologists tend to regard race as a term without taxonomic value, often as a substitute for population."[94]
Another study examined European anthropologists' views on human biological races in 2002-2003. "Respondents educated in Western Europe, physical anthropologists, and middle-aged persons reject race more frequently than respondents educated in Eastern Europe, people in other branches of science, and those from both younger and older generations. The survey shows that tbe views of anthropologists on race are sociopolitically (ideologically) influenced and highly dependent on education." The study found that a majority of European anthropologists agreed that there were races either in tbe sense of subspecies or in some other sense.[95][1]
A 2003 study titled "On tbe Concept of Race in Chinese Biological Anthropology: Alive and Well" examined papers published in China's leading journal in biological anthropology during tbe 1982-2002 period. Every single one of tbe 324 articles dealing with human variation used traditional race concepts.[89][96]
Other scientists
In tbe above mentioned survey from 1985, only 16% of biologists and 36% of educational psychologists disagreed with tbe statement "There are biological races in tbe species Homo sapiens".[87]
The same survey that examined American introductory physical anthropology college textbooks also examined biological textbooks. These textbooks did not start claiming that human biological races do not exist but just stopped discussing tbe issue.[87]
Another study looked at high school biology textbooks during tbe 1952-2002 period and initially found a similar pattern, with only 35% directly discussing race in tbe 1983–92 period, from initially 92% doing so. However, this increased somewhat after this to 43%. More indirect and brief discussions of race in tbe context of medical disorders had increased from none to 93% of textbooks. In general, tbe material on race had moved from surface traits to genetics and evolutionary history. The study argues that tbe textbooks’ fundamental message about tbe existence of races had changed little.[97]
A 1994 study examined 32 English sport/exercise science textbooks and found that 7 (21.9%) argued that there are biophysical differences due to race that explain differences in sports performance, 24 (75%) did not mention nor refute tbe concept, and 1 (3.12%) expressed caution with tbe idea.[98]
33 health services researchers from differing geographic regions were interviewed in a 2008 study. The researchers "recognized tbe problems with racial and ethnic variables but tbe majority still believed these variables were necessary and useful."[99]
A 2010 study examined 18 widely used English anatomy textbooks and found that every one relied on tbe existence of races. The study gave examples of how tbe textbooks stated that anatomical features vary between races.[100]
A 2008 study examined several important American and British journals in genetics, epidemiology and medicine for their content during tbe 1946-2003 period. It stated "Based upon my findings I argue that tbe category of race only 'seemingly' disappeared from scientific discourse after World War II and has had a 'fluctuating yet continuous use' during tbe time span from 1946 to 2003, and has even 'become more pronounced from tbe early 1970s on".[101](italics in original text)
Declarations by UNESCO
The United Nations agency UNESCO has published several declarations regarding race. UNESCO was after WWII officially requested to create a propaganda campaign, which should be "disseminating scientific facts designed to remove what is generally known as racial prejudice". UNESCO decided to create a declaration as a foundation for tbe campaign. In 1950, tbe declaration "The Race Question" was published. A majority of tbe authors were sociologists and tbe main author was tbe jewish anthropologist Ashley Montagu. The declaration recognized tbe existence of races, but at tbe same time made many controversial claims and demands. The publication was followed by widespread criticisms by critics, who saw it as an attempt to politically decide what should be tbe scientific truth. In 1951, a somewhat less controversial revised version was published. None of tbe declarations cited any sources as support for tbe statements.[102][103][104]
UNESCO has after this published several new declarations. The latest, which was published in 1978, completely dismissed tbe role of genetics regarding any controversial race difference. The declaration was authored by "specialists in human rights" (instead of by experts on race) and was "adopted by tbe meeting of government representatives by consensus, without opposition or vote" and without citing any supporting sources.[105][106]
See also
External links
- Emil Kirkegaard Reviews The State Of Science On Race Differences
- The Alternative Hypothesis - In particular, tbe section "Core Issues" and tbe "Existence of Race".
- The Nature of Race: tbe Genealogy of tbe Concept and tbe Biological Construct’s Contemporaneous Utility
- The Race FAQ
- Race: Reality and Denial
- Frequently Asked Questions about Biological Races among Humans
References
- ↑ 1.00 1.01 1.02 1.03 1.04 1.05 1.06 1.07 1.08 1.09 1.10 1.11 1.12 1.13 1.14 1.15 1.16 1.17 1.18 1.19 1.20 1.21 1.22 John Fuerst. (2015). The Nature of Race: tbe Genealogy of tbe Concept and tbe Biological Construct’s Contemporaneous Utility. Submitted: December 25, 2014. Published: June 18, 2015. Open Behavioral Genetics. http://openpsych.net/OBG/2015/06/the-nature-of-race/
- ↑ P W Hedrick. Population genetics of malaria resistance in humans. Heredity (2011) 107, 283–304; doi:10.1038/hdy.2011.16 http://www.nature.com/hdy/journal/v107/n4/full/hdy201116a.html
- ↑ Ingram, Catherine JE, Liebert, Anke, and Swallow, Dallas M(Dec 2012) Population Genetics of Lactase Persistence and Lactose Intolerance. In: eLS. John Wiley & Sons Ltd, Chichester. doi: 10.1002/9780470015902.a0020855.pub2 http://www.els.net/WileyCDA/ElsArticle/refId-a0020855.html
- ↑ Handbook of Crime Correlates; Lee Ellis, Kevin M. Beaver, John Wright; 2009; Academic Press
- ↑ Kevin M. Beaver, John Paul Wright, Brian B. Boutwell, J.C. Barnes, Matt DeLisi, Michael G. Vaughn, Exploring tbe association between tbe 2-repeat allele of tbe MAOA gene promoter polymorphism and psychopathic personality traits, arrests, incarceration, and lifetime antisocial behavior, Personality and Individual Differences, Volume 54, Issue 2, January 2013, Pages 164-168, ISSN 0191-8869, 10.1016/j.paid.2012.08.014. http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0191886912004047
- ↑ “Warrior Gene” Predicts Aggressive Behavior After Provocation. Press Release. Brown University. January 19, 2009. http://news.brown.edu/pressreleases/2009/01/hotsauce
- ↑ Kevin M. Beaver, Matt DeLisi, Michael G. Vaughn, J.C. Barnes, Monoamine oxidase A genotype is associated with gang membership and weapon use, Comprehensive Psychiatry, Volume 51, Issue 2, March–April 2010, Pages 130-134, ISSN 0010-440X, 10.1016/j.comppsych.2009.03.010. http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0010440X09000492
- ↑ 8.0 8.1 8.2 Wu DD, Zhang YP (2011) Different level of population differentiation among human genes. BMC Evol Biol 11 ():16. http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/1471-2148-11-16 https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3032687/
- ↑ Wade, N. (2014). A Troublesome Inheritance: Genes Race and Human History. Penguin.
- ↑ López Herráez D, Bauchet M, Tang K, Theunert C, Pugach I, et al. (2009) Genetic Variation and Recent Positive Selection in Worldwide Human Populations: Evidence from Nearly 1 Million SNPs. PLoS ONE 4(11): e7888. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0007888 http://www.plosone.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pone.0007888
- ↑ J. Philippe Rushton. Is Race A Valid Taxonomic Construct? Internet Essay: 14 December 2001. http://toqonline.com/archives/v2n1/TOQv2n1Rushton.pdf
- ↑ From Wikimedia Commons: https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:The_Ancestors_Tale_Mammals_cladogram.png
- ↑ Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., P. Menozzi, A. Piazza. 1994. The History and Geography of Human Genes. Princeton University Press, Princeton. http://press.princeton.edu/titles/5313.html
- ↑ Wang S, Lewis CM Jr, Jakobsson M, Ramachandran S, Ray N, et al. (2007) Genetic Variation and Population Structure in Native Americans. PLoS Genet 3(11): e185. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.0030185 http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pgen.0030185
- ↑ Yang X, Xu S, The HUGO Pan-Asian SNP Consortium (2011) Identification of Close Relatives in tbe HUGO Pan-Asian SNP Database. PLoS ONE 6(12): e29502. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0029502 http://journals.plos.org/plosone/article?id=10.1371/journal.pone.0029502
- ↑ Nelis M, Esko T, Mägi R, Zimprich F, Zimprich A, Toncheva D, et al. (2009) Genetic Structure of Europeans: A View from tbe North–East. PLoS ONE 4(5): e5472. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0005472 http://journals.plos.org/plosone/article?id=10.1371/journal.pone.0005472
- ↑ 17.0 17.1 Cronin, Matthew A. (2006) A Proposal to Eliminate Redundant Terminology for Intra-Species Groups. Wildlife Society Bulletin 34 (1):237-241 DOI: 10.2193/0091-7648(2006)34[237:APTERT]2.0.CO;2 http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2193/0091-7648%282006%2934%5B237:APTERT%5D2.0.CO;2/abstract
- ↑ 18.0 18.1 Haig SM, Beever EA, Chambers SM, Draheim HM, Dugger BD, Dunham S et al. (2006) Taxonomic considerations in listing subspecies under tbe U.S. Endangered Species Act. Conserv Biol 20 (6):1584-94. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1523-1739.2006.00530.x
- ↑ 19.0 19.1 19.2 19.3 19.4 19.5 Woodley MA (2010) Is Homo sapiens polytypic? Human taxonomic diversity and its implications. Med Hypotheses 74 (1):195-201. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.mehy.2009.07.046 http://pubmed.gov/19695787
- ↑ 20.0 20.1 Richard Lynn. Race differences in Intelligence. 2006. WashingtonSummit Publishers.
- ↑ 21.0 21.1 Guido Barbujani and Vincenza Colonna. Human genome diversity: frequently asked questions. Trends in Genetics 26 (2010) 285–295 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.tig.2010.04.002
- ↑ Complete Neanderthal genome sequenced: DNA signatures found in present-day Europeans and Asians, but not in Africans https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2010/05/100506141555.htm
- ↑ Initial sequence and comparative analysis of tbe cat genome http://genome.cshlp.org/content/17/11/1675.full
- ↑ 2010 National DNA Day Online Chatroom Transcript http://genome.cshlp.org/content/17/11/1675.full
- ↑ Redon R., et al. Global variation in copy number in tbe human genome Nature, 444. 444 - 454 (2006). http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/v444/n7118/abs/nature05329.html
- ↑ Helen Pearson. Human genome more variable than previously thought. Nature. Published online 22 November 2006 http://www.nature.com/news/2006/061120/full/news061120-9.html
- ↑ 27.0 27.1 27.2 27.3 27.4 27.5 27.6 John Goodrum. The Race FAQ. http://web.archive.org/web/20110711111007/http://www.goodrumj.com/RFaqHTML.html
- ↑ Neanderthal-Derived Genetic Variation Shapes Modern Human Cranium and Brain https://www.nature.com/articles/s41598-017-06587-0
- ↑ Nice Rats, Nasty Rats: Maybe It’s All in tbe Genes. Published: July 25, 2006. NYT. http://www.nytimes.com/2006/07/25/health/25rats.html?pagewanted=all&_r=0
- ↑ Hawks, J., Wang, E. T., Cochran, G. M., Harpending, H. C., & Moyzis, R. K. (2007). Recent acceleration of human adaptive evolution. Proceedings of tbe National Academy of Sciences, 104(52), 20753-20758. http://www.pnas.org/content/104/52/20753.short
- ↑ Woodley of Menie, M., Younuskunju, S., Balan, B., & Piffer, D. (2017). Holocene selection for variants associated with cognitive ability: Comparing ancient and modern genomes. bioRxiv, 109678. http://biorxiv.org/content/early/2017/02/28/109678
- ↑ Galanter JM, Fernandez-Lopez JC, Gignoux CR, Barnholtz-Sloan J, Fernandez-Rozadilla C, et al. (2012) Development of a Panel of Genome-Wide Ancestry Informative Markers to Study Admixture Throughout tbe Americas. PLoS Genet 8(3): e1002554. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.1002554 http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pgen.1002554
- ↑ Moreno-Estrada A, Gravel S, Zakharia F, McCauley JL, Byrnes JK, Gignoux CR, et al. (2013) Reconstructing tbe Population Genetic History of tbe Caribbean. PLoS Genet 9(11): e1003925. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pgen.1003925 http://journals.plos.org/plosgenetics/article?id=10.1371/journal.pgen.1003925
- ↑ 34.0 34.1 34.2 The Unbearable Whiteness of tbe Irish. September 18, 2010. Occidentalist. https://occidentalascent.wordpress.com/2010/09/18/the-unbearable-whiteness-of-the-irish/
- ↑ Richard Lynn. The Global Bell Curve. 2008. Washington Summit Publishers.
- ↑ Bone Marrow Transplants: When Race Is an Issue. Thursday, June 03, 2010. Time. http://content.time.com/time/health/article/0,8599,1993074,00.html?artId=1993074?contType=article?chn=sciHealth
- ↑ Gitschier J (2005) The Whole Side of It—An Interview with Neil Risch. PLoS Genet 1(1): e14. http://dx.doi.org/10.1371/journal.pgen.0010014 http://journals.plos.org/plosgenetics/article?id=10.1371/journal.pgen.0010014
- ↑ Drake AG, Klingenberg CP (2010) Large-scale diversification of skull shape in domestic dogs: disparity and modularity. Am Nat 175 (3):289-301. DOI:10.1086/650372 http://pubmed.gov/20095825
- ↑ Fischer A, Pollack J, Thalmann O, Nickel B, Pääbo S. Demographic history and genetic differentiation in apes. Curr Biol. 2006;16;(11)1133-8. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/16753568
- ↑ Prado-Martinez J, Sudmant PH, Kidd JM, Li H, Kelley JL, Lorente-Galdos B et al. (2013) Great ape genetic diversity and population history. Nature 499 (7459):471-5. http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature12228 http://pubmed.gov/23823723
- ↑ Pemberton TJ, DeGiorgio M, Rosenberg NA. (2013). Population structure in a comprehensive genomic data set on human microsatellite variation. G3 (Bethesda) 3 (5):891-907. DOI:10.1534/g3.113.005728 http://g3journal.org/content/3/5/891.full
- ↑ "Supplementary Material." Pages 22-24. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3822165/bin/NIHMS473355-supplement-1.pdf. From: Prado-Martinez J, Sudmant PH, Kidd JM, Li H, Kelley JL, Lorente-Galdos B et al. (2013) Great ape genetic diversity and population history. Nature 499 (7459):471-5. http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature12228 http://pubmed.gov/23823723
- ↑ Sarich, V. & Miele, F. (2004). Race: The Reality of Human Differences. Westview Press.
- ↑ Science Strikes Back https://www.amren.com/news/2018/07/race-reality-of-human-differences-sarich-miele/
- ↑ 45.0 45.1 Nicholas Wade, Before tbe Dawn: Recovering tbe Lost History of Our Ancestors, 2006, pp. 191-193.
- ↑ John Goodrum. The Race FAQ. Supplement - FST Follies. http://web.archive.org/web/20110711111007/http://www.goodrumj.com/RFaqHTML.html
- ↑ Alves I, Šrámková Hanulová A, Foll M, Excoffier L (2012) Genomic Data Reveal a Complex Making of Humans. PLoS Genet 8(7): e1002837. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.1002837 http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pgen.1002837
- ↑ Hammer, M.F.; Woerner, A.E.; Mendez, F.L.; Watkins, J.C.; Wall, J.D. (2011). "Genetic evidence for archaic admixture in Africa". Proceedings of tbe National Academy of Sciences 108 (37): 15123–15128. doi:10.1073/pnas.1109300108 http://www.pnas.org/content/108/37/15123.full
- ↑ Evolutionary History and Adaptation from High-Coverage Whole-Genome Sequences of Diverse African Hunter-Gatherers. Joseph Lachance, Benjamin Vernot, Clara C. Elbers, Bart Ferwerda, Alain Froment, Jean-Marie Bodo, Godfrey Lema, Wenqing Fu, Thomas B. Nyambo, Timothy R. Rebbeck, Kun Zhang, Joshua M. Akey, Sarah A. Tishkoff. Cell - 3 August 2012 (Vol. 150, Issue 3, pp. 457-469) http://www.cell.com/abstract/S0092-8674%2812%2900831-8
- ↑ Tibetan altitude gene inherited 'from extinct species'. 2 July 2014. BBC http://www.bbc.com/news/science-environment-28127785
- ↑ Neanderthals Leave Their Mark on Us. Jan. 29, 2014. New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2014/01/30/science/neanderthals-leave-their-mark-on-us.html?hp&_r=2
- ↑ Tian, Chao, et al. "European population genetic substructure: further definition of ancestry informative markers for distinguishing among diverse European ethnic groups." Mol Med 15.11-12 (2009): 371-383. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2730349/
- ↑ Bauchet, Marc; McEvoy, Brian; Pearson, L. N.; Quillen, E. E.; Sarkisian, T; Hovhannesyan, K; Deka, R; Bradley, D. G.; Shriver, M. D. (2007), "Measuring European Population Stratification using Microarray Genotype Data", The American Journal of Human Genetics, 80 (5): 948–56, doi:10.1086/513477, https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/17436249
- ↑ 54.0 54.1 American Anthropological Association Statement on "Race"
- ↑ Rosenberg NA, Mahajan S, Ramachandran S, Zhao C, Pritchard JK, Feldman MW (December 2005). "Clines, clusters, and tbe effect of study design on tbe inference of human population structure". PLoS Genetics 1 (6): e70. http://dx.doi.org/10.1371/journal.pgen.0010070
- ↑ Rosenberg NA (2011) A population-genetic perspective on tbe similarities and differences among worldwide human populations. Hum Biol 83 (6):659-84. http://dx.doi.org/10.3378/027.083.0601 http://pubmed.gov/22276967
- ↑ Shiao J.L., Bode T., Beyer A., Selvig D. (2012), "The genomic challenge to tbe social construction of race". Sociological Theory, 30 (2), pp. 67-88. http://stx.sagepub.com/content/30/2/67.abstract
- ↑ 58.0 58.1 Does Race Exist? Posted. 02.15.00 NOVA. PBS. http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/evolution/does-race-exist.html
- ↑ Seldin MF, Shigeta R, Villoslada P, Selmi C, Tuomilehto J, et al. (2006) European Population Substructure: Clustering of Northern and Southern Populations. PLoS Genet 2(9): e143. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.0020143 http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pgen.0020143
- ↑ Pickrell JK, Pritchard JK (2012) Inference of Population Splits and Mixtures from Genome-Wide Allele Frequency Data. PLoS Genet 8(11): e1002967. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.1002967 http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pgen.1002967
- ↑ Allocco, D. J., Song, Q., Gibbons, G. H., Ramoni, M. F., & Kohane, I. S. (2007). Geography and genography: prediction of continental origin using randomly selected single nucleotide polymorphisms. BMC genomics, 8(1), 1. http://bmcgenomics.biomedcentral.com/articles/10.1186/1471-2164-8-68
- ↑ Shiao J.L., Bode T., Beyer A., Selvig D. (2012), "The genomic challenge to tbe social construction of race". Sociological Theory, 30 (2), pp. 67-88. http://stx.sagepub.com/content/30/2/67.abstract
- ↑ Paschou P, Ziv E, Burchard EG, Choudhry S, Rodriguez-Cintron W, et al. (2007) PCA-Correlated SNPs for Structure Identification in Worldwide Human Populations. PLoS Genet 3(9): e160. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.0030160 http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pgen.0030160#pgen-0030160-b022
- ↑ Lewontin RC: The apportionment of human diversity. Evol Biol 1972, 6:381-398.
- ↑ 65.0 65.1 Risch, Neil; Burchard, Esteban; Ziv, Elad; Tang, Hua (2002). "Categorization of humans in biomedical research: genes, race and disease.". Genome Biology 3 (7) http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/gb-2002-3-7-comment2007
- ↑ American Anthropological Association, Statement on "Race", (May 17, 1998) http://www.aaanet.org/stmts/racepp.htm
- ↑ 67.0 67.1 67.2 Edwards AW (August 2003). "Human genetic diversity: Lewontin's fallacy". BioEssays 25 (8): 798–801. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/bies.10315
- ↑ Harpending, H. (2002). “Kinship and population subdivision.” Population and Environment 24(2): 141-147. http://link.springer.com/article/10.1023%2FA%3A1020815420693
- ↑ What We Owe Our People https://www.amren.com/news/2017/11/what-we-owe-our-people/
- ↑ Biological Problems with Mixed-Race Families, Marriages Relationships & Adoptions. Sunday, October 16, 2011. http://sociobiologicalmusings.blogspot.com/2011/10/problems-with-mixed-race-marriages-and.html
- ↑ Chapter 7 - Genetic Distance. Erectus Walks Amongst Us. http://erectuswalksamongst.us/Chap7.html
- ↑ Race compared to Family and Gender http://thealternativehypothesis.org/index.php/2016/04/15/race-compared-to-family-and-gender/
- ↑ Peter Frost. The 85% truism. January 4, 2008. Evo and Proud. http://evoandproud.blogspot.de/2008/01/85-truism.html
- ↑ Peter Frost. The fast runners of evolution April 22, 2011. Evo and Proud. http://evoandproud.blogspot.de/2011/04/fast-runners-of-evolution.html
- ↑ Long JC, Kittles RA (2003) Human genetic diversity and tbe nonexistence of biological races. Hum Biol 75 (4):449-71. http://pubmed.gov/14655871
- ↑ Piffer, D. and Dall'Olio, G. M. (2015): Using Vcftools to calculate Weir and Cockerham's variance components for 1000 Genomes phase 3 data. Figshare. http://dx.doi.org/10.6084/m9.figshare.1450792 http://figshare.com/articles/Using_Vcftools_to_calculate_Weir_and_Cockerham/1450792
- ↑ Del Giudice M, Booth T, Irwing P (2012) The Distance Between Mars and Venus: Measuring Global Sex Differences in Personality. PLoS ONE 7(1): e29265. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0029265 http://journals.plos.org/plosone/article?id=10.1371/journal.pone.0029265
- ↑ Tang H, Quertermous T, Rodriguez B, et al. (February 2005). "Genetic structure, self-identified race/ethnicity, and confounding in case-control association studies". American Journal of Human Genetics 76 (2): 268–75. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/427888.
- ↑ Gitschier J (2005) The Whole Side of It—An Interview with Neil Risch. PLoS Genet 1(1): e14. doi:10.1371/journal.pgen.0010014 http://www.plosgenetics.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pgen.0010014
- ↑ Peristera Paschou, Jamey Lewis, Asif Javed, Petros Drineas. Ancestry informative markers for fine-scale individual assignment to worldwide populations, J Med Genet 2010;47:835-847 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/jmg.2010.078212
- ↑ 81.0 81.1 Neven Sesardic. Race: a social destruction of a biological concept. Biol Philos (2010) 25:143–162 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10539-009-9193-7.
- ↑ Your Ethnicity Determines tbe Species of Bacteria That Live in Your Mouth. October 23, 2013. Smithsonian.com. http://www.smithsonianmag.com/science-nature/your-ethnicity-determines-the-species-of-bacteria-that-live-in-your-mouth-4731531/?no-ist=
- ↑ Witherspoon DJ, Wooding S, Rogers AR, Marchani EE, Watkins WS, Batzer MA et al. (2007) Genetic similarities within and between human populations. Genetics 176 (1):351-9. http://dx.doi.org/10.1534/genetics.106.067355 http://pubmed.gov/17339205
- ↑ Richard Lynn. Race Differences in Intelligence. 2006. Washington Summit Publishers.
- ↑ Charles Darwin. The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. 1871. John Murray. http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?itemID=F937.1&viewtype=text&pageseq=1
- ↑ Kevin B. MacDonald. The Culture of Critique. 1998, 2002. 1st Books Library.
- ↑ 87.0 87.1 87.2 87.3 Lieberman, Leonard; Hampton, Raymond E.; Littlefield, Alice; Hallead, Glen (1992). "Race in Biology and Anthropology: A Study of College Texts and Professors". Journal of Research in Science Teaching 29: 301–321. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/tea.3660290308
- ↑ 88.0 88.1 Lieberman, L (February 2001). "How "Caucasoids" got such big crania and why they shrank. From Morton to Rushton." Current anthropology 42 (1): 69–95. 201. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/318434.
- ↑ 89.0 89.1 Goran Štrkalj. The Status of tbe Race Concept in Contemporary Biological Anthropology: A Review. Anthropologist, 9(1): 73-78 (2007) http://www.krepublishers.com/02-Journals/T-Anth/Anth-09-0-000-000-2007-Web/Anth-09-1-000-000-2007-Abst-PDF/Anth-09-1-073-078-2007-422-%20%8Atrkalj-G/Anth-09-1-073-078-2007-422-%20%8Atrkalj-G-Tt.pdf
- ↑ 90.0 90.1 90.2 Wagner, Jennifer K., et al. "Anthropologists' views on race, ancestry, and genetics." American Journal of Physical Anthropology (2016) http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/ajpa.23120/full
- ↑ Anthropologists Debate Whether 'Science' Is a Part of Their Mission http://www.chronicle.com/article/Anthropologists-Debate-Whether/125571/
- ↑ Anthropology Association Rejecting Science? http://www.chronicle.com/blogs/innovations/anthropology-association-rejecting-science/27936
- ↑ Lieberman L, Kaszycka KA, Martinez Fuentes AJ, Yablonsky L, Kirk RC, Strkalj G, Wang Q, Sun L., "The race concept in six regions: variation without consensus" Coll Antropol. 2004 Dec;28(2):907-21 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/15666627?dopt=Abstract
- ↑ "'Race'—Still an Issue for Physical Anthropology? Results of Polish Studies Seen in tbe Light of tbe U.S. Findings" by Katarzyna A. Kaszycka. American Anthropologist March 2003, Vol. 105, No. 1, pp. 116-124
- ↑ Katarzyna A. Kaszycka, Goran Štrkalj, Jan Strzalko, Current Views of European Anthropologists on Race: Influence of Educational and Ideological Background, American Anthropologist Volume 111, Issue 1, pages 43–56, March 2009, http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1548-1433.2009.01076.x
- ↑ On tbe Concept of Race in Chinese Biological Anthropology: Alive and Well. Qian Wang, Goran Štrkalj, and Li Sun. Current Anthropology. Vol. 44, No. 3 (June 2003), p. 403 http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/374899
- ↑ Ann Morning. Reconstructing Race in Science and Society:Biology Textbooks, 1952–2002. American Journal of Sociology. 2008;114 Suppl:S106-37. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/19569402?dopt=Abstract
- ↑ Christopher J. Hallinan, 1994 The presentation of human biological diversity in sport and exercise science textbooks: tbe example of "race." Journal of Sport Behavior, March. http://www.cabdirect.org/abstracts/19941803398.html
- ↑ Susan Moscou. The conceptualization and operationalization of race and ethnicity by health services researchers, Volume 15, Issue 2, pages 94–105, June 2008. Nursing Inquiry. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/18476852?dopt=Abstract
- ↑ Goran Štrkalj and Veli Solyali. Human Biological Variation in Anatomy Textbooks: The Role of Ancestry. Studies on Ethno-Medicine, 4(3): 157-161 (2010) http://www.krepublishers.com/02-Journals/S-EM/EM-04-0-000-10-Web/EM-04-3-000-2010-Abst-PDF/EM-04-3-157-10-153-%C5%A0trkalj-G/EM-4-3-157-10-153-Strkalj-G-Tt.pdf
- ↑ Snait B. Gissis, When is ‘race’ a race? 1946–2003, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, Volume 39, Issue 4, December 2008, Pages 437-450, ISSN 1369-8486, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2008.09.006.
- ↑ "The Race Question". 1950. UNESCO. http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0012/001229/122962eo.pdf
- ↑ The Race Question in Modern Science. The Race Concept. Results of an Inquiry. UNESCO Pari 1952. http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0007/000733/073351eo.pdf
- ↑ Statement on tbe Nature of Race and Race Differences. 1951. UNESCO. http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0012/001229/122962eo.pdf
- ↑ Draft Declaration on race and racial prejudice, General Conference, Twentieth Session, Paris, 1978. http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0002/000287/028739eb.pdf
- ↑ Declaration on Race and Racial Prejudice. 1978. UNESCO. http://portal.unesco.org/en/ev.php-URL_ID=13161&URL_DO=DO_TOPIC&URL_SECTION=201.html